Skip to main content
Log in

Argument ellipsis as external merge after transfer

  • Published:
Natural Language & Linguistic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Argument Ellipsis (AE) is a productive process in Hebrew, but some arguments resist ellipsis—precisely those that do not denote individuals. This constraint, a reflection of a general constraint on variables in natural language, is captured if AE sites are descended from a pro element that is derivationally replaced by a constituent recoverable from the antecedent. This must occur after spellout (to escape pronunciation) but prior to LF (to allow overt subextraction). The proposed analysis integrates novel data as well as recent findings from studies of AE in East Asian languages, and offers a new derivational path to ellipsis, which invokes neither PF-deletion nor LF-copying.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Exceptions exist on both sides. For analyses of AE in terms of PF-deletion, see Cheng (2013); Maeda (2019); and Takahashi (2020).

  2. In Landau (2018), my main concern was to vindicate the AE analysis over its competitors—pro-drop, Ā-variable and V-stranding VP ellipsis (VSVPE). Most of the data cited in this section is neutral between AE and VSVPE, as it is not my purpose to reproduce the earlier arguments against VSVPE here. Nonetheless, Sect. 5 returns to this debate with a new set of contrasts.

  3. In Sect. 6.2 I return to AE of clausal complements.

  4. See Park 1997; Oku 1998; Kim 1999; Takahashi 2006, 2008, 2013, 2014; Saito 2007, 2017; Aoun and Li 2008; Abe 2009; Cheng 2013; Simpson et al. 2013; Duguine 2014; Lee 2014; Sato 2014, 2015, 2016; Cyrino and Lopes 2016; Sato and Karimi 2016; Bailyn 2017; Rasekhi 2018; Sato 2019; Han et al. 2020; Sakamoto 2020; Soltan 2020.

  5. The proposal, of course, assumes that Japanese and similar radical pro-drop languages do not employ null determiners; thus, property-meanings can be converted to individual-meanings only post-syntactically.

  6. In support of this analogy, Saito (2007, 2017) notes that AE and pro similarly extend to the same kind of PPs—locative and temporal PPs but not manner and reason PPs. However, if absence of syntactic checking of uninterpretable features were sufficient to license AE (= LF-copying), PPs and CPs—which do not check Case—would be eligible to ellipsis in English-type languages, contrary to fact (see Cheng 2013: 190).

  7. (8c) is possibly false as well: Basque manifests AE of object despite the presence of object agreement (Duguine 2014). Since the status of the anti-agreement parameter of Saito (2007, 2017) is not at the focus of the present article, I will not discuss it any further.

  8. Landman (2006: 98) only briefly discusses predicative so (e.g., I thought she would be happy, but she certainly doesn’t seem so), suggesting a parallel treatment, in analogy to that way. An alternative analysis for all predicative pro-forms would be to assume that they denote “nominalized properties” in Chierchia’s (1984, 1985) sense, that is, the individual correlates of properties.

  9. I am oversimplifying Poole’s account. Poole proposes that traces must range over individuals (the Trace Interpretation Constraint, TIC) and argues (Poole 2017: 228) that this constraint cannot be subsumed under the NHTV because traces are converted to anaphoric definite descriptions that contain a variable (Fox 2003; Sauerland 2004). The TIC has the effect of ruling out both property-type traces and generalized-quantifier (GQ) type ones. GQ-traces (of type < <e,t>,t>) would allow semantic reconstruction (for scope) to dissociate from syntactic reconstruction (for binding); but previous work has established that the two go together (Romero 1998; Fox 1999). Nevertheless, Poole acknowledges that the NHTV and TIC should be unified at some deeper level. From the perspective of the present discussion, AE sites start out their derivational live hosting a pro-variable (Sect. 6), so it makes sense to keep to Landman’s framework and the NHTV.

  10. Demonstrative pronouns are acceptable in antipronominal environments (e.g., Irene liked the name Snowflake, and she called the cat that/*it; Poole 2017: 31). Drawing on various syntactic and semantic considerations, Poole (2017: 217) argues that they are type-shifted to denote a property. Alternatively, demonstrative pronouns are phrasal modifiers (see Leu 2007 and the references therein), already interpreted as predicates. When used referentially (e.g., I saw that), they modify a null noun denoting THING.

  11. There is some inter-speaker variation in the extent to which individual examples are judged acceptable, yet the set in (28)–(31) is overall clearly distinguishable from the set in (22)–(27), which is ungrammatical for all speakers. The attested variation in AE within decomposable idioms possibly reflects the fact that “decomposability” is a gradient scale, and different speakers may draw the line at different points along that scale.

  12. Dative pronouns in Hebrew are necessarily human-denoting (Francez 2006), ruling out pronominalization of the idiom chunk in (26).

  13. As to the difference between ellipsis and pronominalization of the idiom chunk, Sato claims it follows from the LF-copying analysis of AE: “The body part in the antecedent clause… cannot serve as a suitable target for LF-copy because it has already become an unanalyzable part of the whole atomic VP by the time when the elided part in the elliptical clause is to be filled by LF-copy” (Sato 2020: 272), but “a pronoun (overt or null) can be employed even when its antecedent is a part of a syntactically derived complex predicate at LF” (Sato 2020: 273). This seems like a description of a puzzle rather than a solution. What allows discourse anaphora to access an “unanalyzable part of the whole atomic VP”? Note that truly unanalyzable units create anaphoric islands (Postal 1969; Ward et al. 1991). On the present approach, no systematic discrepancy is expected between the accessibility of idiom chunks to pronouns and to silent constituents that replace pronouns.

  14. For arguments that English so/thus are not pro-adverbs, but rather denote properties of realizations of event kinds, see Landman (2006: 83–92).

  15. Hebrew middle morphology is sometimes syncretic with passive morphology, as in (47b). The second clause in the latter thus has an irrelevant (and absurd) passive reading without the adverb – short poems are not written.

  16. An additional case in point involves frequency and duration adverbs in Chinese, which, according to the prevalent view, occupy a complement position in the VP (Huang 1982; Li 1990; Soh 1998). When co-occurring with an object, they trigger verb doubling. AE may then target the object but not the adverb, which is, in fact, obligatory (Li 2014: 55).

    1. (i)
      figure av
  17. All the examples in (50)–(52) are from Adger (1994: 99–103), except (51b).

  18. The preposition ke- ‘as’ does not take weak pronouns as complements so this test cannot be applied in (56). A strong demonstrative pronoun would be acceptable (ke-xaze ‘as such’).

  19. I am aware of two potential counterexamples: ellipsis of an AP-complement of become in Japanese (Takahashi 2006: ex. 44b) and AP ellipsis inside a small clause in Serbo-Croatian (Bošković 2018: 25, fn. 29). Future research should carefully analyze such examples to evaluate their import.

  20. The crucial difference, according to Landau (2020b), is whether the raised verb crosses a spellout domain (VP but not AuxP). When it does, its trace can no longer mediate the deletion instruction to PF.

  21. Phrasal pro-forms may, of course, denote outside the domain of individuals, as their basic semantic type is shifted by functors they combine with (see fn. 10). Note that (70) predicts not only that AE sites cannot denote properties but also that they cannot denote generalized quantifiers, aligning with Poole’s (2017) constraint on trace denotations. This is indeed true, as I briefly demonstrate in Sect. 7, although the full case is laid out in Landau (to appear).

  22. The present proposal associates pro-forms with reconstructed syntactic structure, but it does not imply that they cannot be associated with PF-deletion in other elliptical constructions. Indeed, certain varieties of VP ellipsis have been analyzed precisely in such terms: PF-deletion of a VP node that strands an overt pro-form (Baltin 2012 on do so anaphora in English; Hauser et al. 2007 and Bentzen et al. 2013 on gøre det/gjøre det ‘do it’ anaphora in Danish and Norwegian, respectively). The do so case is fundamentally different in that the pro-form so is not a surrogate of the surface anaphor at all; rather, its complement is the target of ellipsis. The Scandinavian constructions do involve what seems like a property-anaphor, det, in the complement position of the light verb, but this is an illusion. Throughout the derivation and up to LF, the VP is a full syntactic structure, and det is inserted only at PF. Thus, det is not a syntactic or semantic variable, and perforce is not subject to the Generalized NHTV. Finally, the predicate anaphor le in French displays clear properties of a surface anaphor, e.g., allowing subextraction (Sportiche 1995); Sportiche, in fact, takes it to be a propositional anaphor (subsuming both the elided predicate and the extracted subject). Either way, it does not fall under the NHTV.

  23. (71b) can be viewed as a mirror-image of the early Pronominalization transformation of the 1960s: while the latter converted an NP into a pronoun under identity with antecedent NP, the former converts a pronoun into a DP under identity with an antecedent DP.

  24. See Landau (2018: ex. 50) for Hebrew data on QR out of elided arguments and (a rare case of) overt subextraction out of an elided DP.

  25. This view receives interesting support from Korean, where CP complements can undergo AE if and only if they are nominal (featuring a nominalizer and/or a case marker, the latter sometimes optional), a property that also underlies their susceptibility to pronominalization (Sohn 2012).

  26. The interpretation of extraction data with topic-marked (wa) constituents is not entirely settled; see Sakamoto (2020: 62, fn. 1) and Takahashi (2020: fn. 20).

  27. On a Late Insertion model, the difference between the two is the presence of spellout instructions at the terminal nodes of the syntactic object vs. their absence from the LF-object (see Saab 2022, for a recent implementation).

  28. Chomsky further suggests that semantic interpretation is cyclically synchronized with phonological spellout, so that a single transfer operation feeds both interfaces at every phase level. I take issue with this assumption below.

  29. In this respect the present proposal is also different from Fortin (2011), where Sluicing is analyzed as copying of the LF structure of an antecedent TP. Fortin assimilates this operation to sideward movement (Nunes 2004), a nontrivial step, since sideward movement requires access to a syntactic object embedded inside a bigger one; this powerful device is not needed on the present analysis. In addition, sideward movement is wedded to a complex algorithm responsible for PF-deletion of copies unrelated by c-command. Since the mechanism of “obtaining silence” in AE is fundamentally different from PF-deletion, I will not pursue this analogy here.

  30. Can pro-replacement occur before transfer? If it can, the result would not be distinguishable from direct Merge of the argument, so the point is moot. A reviewer also asks whether EMAT can replace an overt pronoun. Theoretically, this should be possible; the replacement would only affect LF, keeping the overt pronoun at PF intact. This way of generating overt surface anaphors would be a mirror-image of overt surface anaphors generated at PF (see fn. 22). In fact, pronominal clitics in Catalan and Serbo-Croatian may well instantiate this option (Quer and Rosseló 2013; Runić 2014; Bošković 2018).

  31. I return below to the question of what determines whether a language allows AE or not.

  32. This raises the intriguing possibility that unconstrained EMAT may apply in inner speech, where RoE is not at issue, as the content of merged arguments, whether overt or not, is always recoverable to the speaker. It is well-known that inner speech has phonological structure (Langland-Hassan and Vicente 2018), which indicates that its constituents undergo transfer to PF (later aborted en route to the speech articulators). The often-made observation that it is more fragmentary and abridged than overt speech may be partially explained in terms of pervasive use of EMAT.

  33. Parallelism domains are relevant to recoverability whenever the ellipsis site contains a variable bound from the outside (Takahashi and Fox 2005), whether a pronoun (77) or a trace (78). There are more recent reformulations of this concept, but the choice among them is not relevant for the present concerns.

  34. Giannakidou and Merchant’s (1997) explanation is syntactic, though, unlike the present semantic explanation. They assume that strong quantifiers reside in D whereas weak ones attach below it. Because D is the head-licensor of nominal ellipsis, it cannot be included in the ellipsis site. Notice that this account cannot generalize to languages where AE applies to definite (hence, full DP) arguments, which nonetheless display a parallel ban on ellipsis of strong quantifiers. Below I sugggest that head-licensing is anyway operative in PF-deletion only, so it does not constrain AE (which is derived by EMAT).

  35. See Ahn and Cho (2011) for a parallel observation in Korean.

  36. See Tomioka (2014: 257) for the original observation in Japanese.

References

  • Abe Jun. 2009. Identification of null arguments in Japanese. In The dynamics of the language faculty: Perspectives from linguistics and cognitive neuroscience, ed. Hiroto Hoshi, 135–162. Tokyo: Kuroshio Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adger, David. 1994. Functional heads and interpretation. Ph.D diss., University of Edinburgh.

  • Aelbrecht, Lobke. 2010. The syntactic licensing of ellipsis. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aelbrecht, Lobke, and William Harwood. 2015. To be or not to be elided: VP ellipsis revisited. Lingua 153: 66–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ahn, Hee-Don, and Sungeun Cho. 2011. Notes on apparent DP ellipsis: A reply to Lee and Kim (2010). Korean Journal of Linguistics 36: 457–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aoun, Joseph, and Yen-hui Audrey Li. 2008. Ellipsis and missing objects. In Foundational isues in generative grammar, eds. Robert Freidin, Carlos Peregrín Otero, and Maria Luisa Zubizarreta, 251–274. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailyn, John F. 2017. Against a VP ellipsis account of Russian verb-stranding constructions. In Studies in Japanese and Korean historical and theoretical linguistics and beyond: Festschrift presented to John B. Whitman, eds. Alexander Vovin and William McClure. Vol. 16 of Languages of Asia, 93–109. Boston: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, Mark. 2003. Lexical categories: Verbs, nouns and adjectives. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Baltin, Mark. 2012. Deletion versus pro-forms: An overly simple dichotomy? Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 30: 381–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bentzen, Kristine, Jason Merchant, and Peter Svenonius. 2013. Deep properties of surface pronouns: Pronominal predicate anaphors in Norwegian and German. The Journal of Comparative Germanic Linguistics 16: 97–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bošković, Željko. 2014. Now I’m a phase, now I’m not a phase: On the variability of phases with extraction and ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry 45: 27–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bošković, Željko. 2018. On pronouns, clitic doubling, and argument ellipsis: Argument ellipsis as predicate ellipsis. English Linguistics 35: 1–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, Gregory N. 1977. Reference to kinds in English. PhD diss., University of Massachusetts.

  • Cheng, Hsu-Te. 2013. Argument ellipsis, classifier phrases, and the DP parameter, PhD diss., University of Connecticut.

  • Chierchia, Gennaro. 1984. Topics in the syntax and semantics of infinitives and gerunds. PhD diss., University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

  • Chierchia, Gennaro. 1985. Formal semantics and the grammar of predication. Linguistic Inquiry 16: 417–443.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, Gennaro. 1998. Reference to kinds across language. Natural Language Semantics 6: 339–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 1993. A Minimalist Program for linguistic theory. In The view from building 20: Essays in linguistics in honor of Sylvain Bromberger, eds. Ken Hale and Samuel Jay Keyser, 1–52. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 2004. Beyond explanatory adequacy. In Structures and beyond: The cartography of syntactic structures (vol. 3), ed. Adriana Belletti, 10–131. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 2008. On phases. In In foundational issues in linguistic theory: Essays in honor of Jean-Roger Vergnaud, eds. Robert Freidin, Carlos Peregrín Otero, and Maria Luisa Zubizarreta, 133–166. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 2013. Problems of projection. Lingua 130: 33–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 2019. Some puzzling foundational issues: The reading program. Catalan Journal of Linguistics, Special Issue: Generative Syntax. Questions, Crossroads, and Challenges, 263–285.

  • Chomsky, Noam. 2020. The UCLA lectures. Ms., University of Arizona.

  • Chomsky, Noam, and Howard Lasnik. 1993. The theory of principles and parameters. In Syntax: An International Handbook of Contemporary Research, eds. Joachim Jacobs, Arnim von Stechow, Wofgang Sternefeld, and Theo Vennemann, 506–569. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chung, Sandra, William A. Ladusaw, and James McCloskey. 1995. Sluicing and logical form. Natural Language Semantics 3: 239–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Constant, Noah. 2012. Witnessable quantifiers license type-e meaning: Evidence from contrastive topic, equatives and supplements. In Proceedings of SALT 22, ed. Anca Chereches, 286–306. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cyrino, Sonia. 2021. On the syntax of null objects in Brazilian Portuguese. Handout of talk delivered at the conference Null Objects from a Crosslinguistic and Development Perspective. Portugal: University of Minho. January 2021.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cyrino, Sonia, and Ruth Lopes. 2016. Null objects and ellipsis in Brazilian Portuguese. The Linguistic Review 33: 483–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cyrino, Sonia, and Gabriela Matos. 2006. Null complement Aanaphora in Romance: Deep or surface Anaphora? In Romance Languages and Linguistic Theory 2004, eds. Jenny Doetjes and Paz González, 95–120. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Depiante, Marcela A. 2001. On null complement anaphora in Spanish and Italian. Probus 13: 193–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doron, Edit. 1990. V-movement and VP-ellipsis. Ms., The Hebrew University of Jerusalem.

  • Doron, Edit. 1999. V-movement and VP-ellipsis. In Fragments: Studies in ellipsis and gapping, eds. Elabbas Benmamoun and Shalom Lappin, 124–140. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duguine, Maia. 2014. Argument ellipsis: A unitary approach to pro-drop. The Linguistic Review 3: 515–549.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elbourne, Paul. 2005. The semantics of ellipsis. Structure 3: 63–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, Samuel D., Hisatsugu Kitahara, and Daniel T. Seely. 2012. Structure building that can’t be. In Ways of structure building, eds. Myriam Uribe-Etxebarria and Vidal Valmala, 253–270. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fadlon, Julie, Julia Horvath, Tal Siloni, and Ken Wexler. 2018. The acquisition of Hebrew idioms: Stages, internal composition, and implications for storage. Glossa 3(1). Art. 99.

  • Fortin, Catherine R. 2011. We need LF-copying: A few good reasons why. In Proceedings WCCFL 28, eds. Mary B. Washburn, Katherine McKinney-Bock, Erika Varis, Ann Sawyer, and Barbara Tomaszewicz, 87–95. Somerville: Cascadilla Proceedings Project.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Danny. 1999. Reconstruction, binding theory and the interpretation of chains. Linguistic Inquiry 30: 157–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Danny. 2000. Economy and semantic interpretation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Danny. 2003. On logical form. In Minimalist syntax, ed. Randall Hendrick, 82–123. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Francez, Itamar. 2006. Possessors, goals and the classification of ditransitive predicates: Evidence from Hebrew. In Empirical issues in syntax and semantics 6. eds. Olivier Bonami, and Patricia Cabredo Hofherr, 137–154. Paris: Presses Universitaires de Paris-Sorbonne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Funakoshi, Kenshi. 2016. Verb-stranding Verb Phrase ellipsis in Japanese. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 25: 113–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giannakidou, Anastasia, and Jason Merchant. 1997. On the interpretation of null indefinite objects in Greek. Studies in Greek Linguistics 17: 141–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, Lotus M. 2005. Verb-stranding VP ellipsis: A cross-linguistic study. PhD diss., McGill University.

  • Gribanova, Vera. 2013. A new argument for verb-stranding Verb Phrase ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry 44: 145–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gribanova, Vera. 2020. Predicate formation and verb-stranding ellipsis in Uzbek. Glossa 5(1). Art. 124.

  • Grimshaw, Jane, and Armin Mester. 1988. Light verbs and theta-marking. Linguistic Inquiry 19: 205–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Han, Chung-hye, Kim Kyeong-min, Keir Koulton, and Jeffery Lidz. 2020. Null objects in Korean: Experimental evidence for the argument ellipsis analysis. Linguistic Inquiry 51: 319–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harley, Heidi. 2007. One-replacement, unaccusativity, acategorial roots, and bare phrase structure. Harvard Working Papers in Linguistics 11: 637–678.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, Michael, Line Mikkelsen, and Maziar Toosanvardani. 2007. Verb Phrase pronominalization in Danish: Deep or surface anaphora? In Proceedings of the 34 Western Conference on Linguistics, eds. Erin Brainbridge and Brian Agbayani, 183–195. Fresno, CA: Department of Linguistics, California State University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heycock, Caroline. 1995. Asymmetries in reconstruction. Linguistic Inquiry 26: 547–570.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huang, C.-T. James. 1982. Logical relations in Chinese and the theory of grammar. PhD diss., MIT.

  • Johnson, Kyle. 2001. What VP-ellipsis can do, and what it can’t, but not why. In The handbook of contemporary syntactic theory, eds. Mark Baltin and Chris Collins, 439–479. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Kyle. 2019. Gapping and stripping. In The Oxford handbook of ellipsis, eds. Jeoren van Craenenbroeck and Tanja Temmerman, 562–604. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jung, Dukkyo. 2003. Complex predicates under the vP hypothesis. In Proceedings of the Korean Society for Languge and Information Conference, Vol. 06, 118–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kayne, Richard S. 1984. Connectedness and binary branching. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, Soowon. 1999. Sloppy/strict identity, empty objects, and NP ellipsis. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 8: 255–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, Young-Hoon. 2019. Syntactic constraints on argument ellipsis in Korean, Master thesis, Seoul National University.

  • Kratzer, Angelika. 2006. Decomposing attitude verbs. Handout of talk honoring Anita Mittwoch, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem.

  • Kurafuji, Takeo. 2019. A choice function approach to null arguments. Linguistics and Philosophy 42: 3–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landau, Idan. 2018. Missing objects in Hebrew: Argument ellipsis, not VP ellipsis. Glossa 3(1): Art. 76, 1–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landau, Idan. 2020a. On the non-existence of verb-stranding VP-ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry 51: 341–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landau, Idan. 2020b. Constraining head-stranding ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry 51: 281–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landau, Idan. 2021. Ellipsis with a coordinated antecedent: An alternative to V-stranding VP-ellipsis. Studia Linguistica 75: 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landau, Idan. To appear. Type-restricted argument ellipsis and generalized quantifiers. Linguistic Inquiry.

  • Landman, Meredith. 2006. Variables in natural language. PhD diss., University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

  • Langland-Hassan, Peter, and Agustin Vicente, eds. 2018. Inner speech: New voices, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee, Wooseung. 2014. Argumental gaps in Korean. The Linguistic Association of Korea Journal 1–29.

  • Lee, Wooseung. 2016. Argument ellipsis vs. V-stranding ellipsis in Korean: Evidence from disjunction. Linguistic Research 33: 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leu, Thomas. 2007. These HERE demonstratives. University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics 13: 141–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Li, Yen-Hui Audrery. 1990. Order and constituency in Mandarin Chinese. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Li, Yen-Hui Audrery. 2014. Born empty. Lingua 151: 43–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liefke, Kristina, and Markus Werning. 2018. Evidence for single-type semantics. An alternative to e/t-based dual-type semantics. Journal of Semantics 35: 639–685.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipták, Anikó, and Güliz Güneş, eds. 2022. The derivational timing of ellipsis, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Llombart-Huesca, Amàlia. 2002. Anaphoric one and NP-ellipsis. Studia Linguistica 56: 59–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lobeck, Anne. 1995. Ellipsis: Functional heads, licensing, and identification. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lobeck, Anne. 1999. VP ellipsis and the Minimalist Program: Some speculations and proposals. In Fragments: Studies in ellipsis and gapping, eds. Shalom Lappin and Elabbas Benmamoun, 98–123. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maeda, Masako. 2019. Argument ellipsis and scope economy in Japanese. Syntax 22: 419–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marušič, Franc, Petra Mišmaš, Vesna Pleničar, and Tina Šuligoj. 2018. Surviving sluicing. In Advances in Slavic linguistics 2016, eds. Denisa Lenertová, Roland Meyer, Radek Šimík, and Luka Szucsich, 193–215. Berlin: Language Science Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matushansky, Ora. 2008. On the linguistic complexity of proper names. Linguistics and Philosophy 21: 573–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May, Robert. 1977. The grammar of quantification. PhD diss., MIT.

  • Merchant, Jason. 2001. The Syntax of silence: Sluicing, islands and the theory of ellipsis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merchant, Jason. 2004. Fragments and ellipsis. Linguistics and Philosophy 27: 661–738.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merchant, Jason. 2018. Verb-stranding predicate ellipsis in Greek, implicit arguments, and ellipsis-internal focus. In A reasonable way to proceed: Essays in honor of Jim McCloskey, eds. Jason Merchant, Line Mikkelsen, Deniz Rudin, and Kelsei Sasaki, 229–270. Santa Cruz: University of Santa Cruz

    Google Scholar 

  • Merchant, Jason. 2019. Ellipsis: A survey of analytical approaches. In Handbook of ellipsis, eds. Jeroen van Craenenbroeck and Tanja Temmerman, 19–45. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Moltmann, Friedrike. 2013. Abstract objects and the semantics of natural language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moulton, Keir. 2019. Adverbs in VP ellipsis: An experimental investigation of antecedent selection. Canadian Journal of Linguistics 64: 475–508.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulton, Keir. 2020. Remarks on propositional nominalization. In Nominalizations: 50 years on from Chomsky’s remarks, eds. Hagit Borer and Artemis Alexiadou, 255–276. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Andrew. 2018. Surface properties of anaphoric one. Handout of talk delivered at LAGB Annual Meeting, University of Sheffield.

  • Ngonyani, Deo. 1996. VP ellipsis in Ndendeule and Swahili applicatives. In Syntax at sunset (UCLA Working Papers in Linguistics), eds. Edward Garrett and Felicia Lee, 109–128. Lost Angeles: UCLA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nunberg, Geoffry, Ivan Sag, and Thomas Wasow. 1994. Idioms. Language 70: 491–538.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nunes, Jairo. 2004. Linearization of chains and sideward movement. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ohtaka, Akane. 2021. A hybrid analysis of null argument constructions in Japanese. University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics 27: 179–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oku, Satoshi. 1998. A theory of selection and reconstruction in the Minimalist perspective. PhD diss., University of Connecticut.

  • Oku, Satoshi. 2016. A note on ellipsis-resistant constituents. Nanzan Linguistics: Research Results and Activities 11: 57–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Panitz, Ezekiel J. 2018. Argument ellipsis and strong Islands. PhD diss., University College London.

  • Park, Myung-Kwan. 1997. The syntax of VP ellipsis in Korean. Language Research 33: 629–648.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, Barbara H. 1997. Genitives: A case study. In Handbook of logic and language, eds. Johan Van Benthem and Alice ter Meulen, 464–470. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poole, Ethan. 2017. Movement and the semantic type of traces. PhD diss., University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

  • Portelance, Eva. 2020. Genuine verb stranding vP-ellipsis in Lithuanian. In Proceedings of NELS 50, eds. Mariam Asatryan, Yixiao Song, and Ayana Whitmal, 59–72. Amherst: GLSA Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Postal, Paul. 1969. Anaphoric Islands. In Proceedings of CLS 5, eds. Robert I. Binnick, Alice Davison, Georgia M. Green, and Jerry L. Morgan, 209–239. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Postal, Paul. 1994. Contrasting extraction types. Journal of Linguistics 30: 159–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potts, Christopher. 2002. The lexical semantics of parenthetical-as and appositive-which. Syntax 5: 55–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quer, Josep, and Joana Rosseló. 2013. On sloppy readings, ellipsis and pronouns. In Information structure and agreement, eds. Camacha Taboada and Maria Victoria, 337–370. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rasekhi, Vahideh. 2018. Ellipsis and information structure: Evidence from Persian. PhD diss., Stony Brook University.

  • Rizzi, Luigi. 1990. Relativized Minimality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romero, Maribel. 1998. Focus and reconstruction in the interpretation of Wh-phrases. PhD diss., University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

  • Ross, John R. 1969. Guess who. In Proceedings of CLS 5, eds. Robert I. Binnik, Alice Davidson, Georgia M. Green, and Jerry L. Morgan, 252–286. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Runić, Jelena. 2014. A new look at clitics, clitic doubling, and argument ellipsis. PhD diss., University of Massachusetts, Amherst.

  • Saab, Andrès. 2022. Grammatical silences from syntax to morphology: A model for the timing of ellipsis. In The derivational timing of ellipsis, eds. Anikó Lipták and Güliz Günes, 170–224. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sag, Ivan. 1976. A note on Verb Phrase deletion. Lingiuistic Inquiry 7: 664–670.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saito, Mamoru. 2007. Notes on East Asian argument ellipsis. Language Research 43: 203–227.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saito, Mamoru. 2017. Ellipsis. In Handbook of Japanese syntax, eds. Masayoshi Shibatani, Shigeru Miyagawa, and Hisashi Noda, 701–750. Berlin: DeGruyter Mouton.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Saito, Mamoru, and Duk-Ho An. 2010. A comparative syntax of ellipsis in Japanese and Korean. In Proceedings of the 6th Workshop on Altaic Formal linguistics (WAFL 6), eds. Hiroki Maezawa and Azusa Yokogoshi. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics, 287–307.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sakamoto, Yuta. 2020. Silently structured silent argument. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sato, Yosuke. 2014. Argument ellipsis in colloquial Singapore English and the anti-agreement hypothesis. Journal of Linguistics 50: 365–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sato, Yosuke. 2015. Argument ellipsis in Javanese and voice agreement. Studia Linguistica 69: 58–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sato, Yosuke. 2016. Remarks on the parameters of argument ellipsis: A new perspective from colloquial Singapore English. Syntax 19: 392–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sato, Yosuke. 2019. Comparative syntax of argument ellipsis in languages without agreement: A case study with Mandarin Chinese. Journal of Linguistics 55: 643–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sato, Yosuke. 2020. Idioms, argument ellipsis and LF-copy. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 29: 259–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sato, Yosuke, and Simin Karimi. 2016. Subject-object asymmetries in Persian argument ellipsis and the anti-agreement theory. Glossa 1: 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sauerland, Uli. 2004. The interpretation of traces. Natural Language Semantics 12: 63–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzchild, Roger. 2005. Measure phrases as modifiers of adjectives. Recherches linguistiques de Vincennes 34: 207–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scontras, Gregory. 2014. The semantics of measurement. PhD diss., Harvard University.

  • Şener, Serkan, and Daiko Takahashi. 2010. Ellipsis of arguments in Japanese and Turkish. Nanzan Linguistics 6: 79–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, Andrew, Arumina Choudhury, and Mythili Menon. 2013. Argument ellipsis and the licensing of covert nominals in Bangla, Hindi and Malayalam. Lingua 134: 103–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soh, Hooi Ling. 1998. Object scrambling in Chinese. PhD diss., MIT.

  • Sohn, Keun-Won. 2012. Apparent CP deletion and DP relatedness. Linguistic Research 29: 107–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soltan, Usama. 2020. On null objects in Egyptian Arabic. Brill’s Journal of Afroasiatic Languages and Linguistics 12: 204–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sportiche, Dominique. 1995. French predicative clitics and clause structure. In Small clauses: Syntax and semantics 28, eds. Anna Cardinaletti and Maria Teresa Guasti, 287–324. New York: Academic Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Takahashi, Daiko. 2006. Apparent parasitic gaps and null arguments in Japanese. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 15: 1–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Takahashi, Daiko. 2008. Quantificational null objects and argument ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry 39: 307–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Takahashi, Daiko. 2013. Argument ellipsis in Japanese and Malayalam. Nanzan Linguistics 9: 173–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Takahashi, Daiko. 2014. Argument ellipsis, anti-agreement and scrambling. In Japanese syntax in comparative perspective, ed. Mamuro Saito, 88–116. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Takahashi, Daiko. 2020. Derivational argument ellipsis. The Linguistic Review 37: 47–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Takahashi, Shoichi, and Danny Fox. 2005. MaxElide and the re-binding problem. In Proceedings of SALT 15, eds. Effi Georgala and Jonathan Howell, 223–240. Ithaca: CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Takano, Yuji. 1995. Predicate fronting and internal subjects. Linguistic Inquiry 26: 327–340.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tancredi, Christopher. 1992. Deletion, deaccenting and presupposition. PhD diss., MIT.

  • Temmerman, Tanja. 2019. When the sluice is not alone: On the syntax of WH+non-WH sluicing in Dutch. Presentation at the Sluicing and Ellipsis at 50 conference, University of Chicago.

  • Tomioka, Satoshi. 2003. The semantics of Japanese null pronouns and its cross-linguistic implications. In The interfaces: Deriving and interpreting omitted structures, eds. Kerstin Schwabe and Susanne Winkler, 321–339. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tomioka, Satoshi. 2014. Remarks on missing arguments in Japanese. In Proceedings of FAJL 7, eds. Shigeto Kawahara and Mika Igarashi, 251–264. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Craenenbroeck, Jeroen. 2010. The syntax of ellipsis: Evidence from Dutch dialects. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vikner, Carl, and Per Anker Jensen. 2002. A semantic analysis of the English genitive. Interaction of lexical and formal semantics. Studia Linguistica 56: 191–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, Gregory, Richard Sproat, and Gail McKoon. 1991. A pragmatic analysis of so-called anaphoric Islands. Language 67: 439–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wasow, Thomas. 1972. Anaphoric relations in English. PhD diss., MIT.

  • Williams, Edwin. 1977. Discourse and logical form. Lingiuistic Inquiry 8: 101–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winter, Yoad. 2005. Cross-categorial restrictions on measure phrase modification. Linguistics and Philosophy 28: 233–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wurmbrand, Susi. 2017. Stripping and topless complements. Linguisic Inquiry 48: 341–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yoshimura, Noriko. 1992. Scrambling and anaphora in Japanese. PhD diss., University of Southern California.

Download references

Acknowledgements

Earlier versions of this study have been presented at the linguistics colloquia of the Hebrew University of Jerusalem, the University of Geneva, the “You’re on Mute!” ellipsis seminar organized by Gary Thoms at NYU and GLOW 45 at Queen Mary University of London. I am grateful to the audiences in all these venues for their helpful feedback, as well as to two anonymous NLLT reviewers. This research was supported by the Israel Science Foundation (grant No. 495/20).

Funding

Israel Science Foundation Grant number 495/20.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Idan Landau.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Landau, I. Argument ellipsis as external merge after transfer. Nat Lang Linguist Theory 41, 793–845 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-022-09552-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-022-09552-3

Keywords

Navigation