Publications

2020

Landau, Idan. 2020. “Nonobligatory Control With Communication Verbs: New Evidence and Implications”. Linguistic Inquiry 51 (1): 75-96. https://doi.org/10.1162/ling\_a\_00332.

When occurring without their goal argument, communication verbs induce two types of control: obligatory control (OC) by the implicit goal, or nonobligatory control (NOC) by a salient antecedent. Arguments are presented to demonstrate that the two are genuinely distinct, and furthermore, that the NOC option is not reducible to embedded imperatives. The two types of control implicate the same grammatical representations, the single difference being the choice of the context of evaluation for PRO (fixed as the reported context in OC, free in NOC). Finally, evidence is presented (from VP-ellipsis) that reference to deictic antecedents in NOC is not direct but mediated via grammatically present entities (SPEAKER and ADDRESSEE functions).

Landau, Idan. 2020. “On the Nonexistence of Verb-Stranding VP-Ellipsis”. Linguistic Inquiry 51 (2): 341-65. https://doi.org/10.1162/ling\_a\_00346.

An increasingly popular analysis of object gap sentences in many languages derives them in two steps: (a) V-raising out of VP, and (b) VP-ellipsis of the remnant, stranding the verb (V-stranding VP-ellipsis, VSVPE). For Hebrew, Hindi, Russian, and Portuguese, I show this analysis to be inadequate. First, it undergenerates elliptical objects in various environments, and second, it overgenerates nonexisting adjunct-including readings. For all the problematic data, simple argument ellipsis provides a unified explanation. The absence of VSVPE in languages that do allow V-raising and Aux-stranding VP-ellipsis raises an intriguing problem for theories addressing the interaction of head movement and ellipsis.

Landau, Idan. 2020. “Constraining Head-Stranding Ellipsis”. Linguistic Inquiry 51 (2): 281-318. https://doi.org/10.1162/ling\_a\_00347.

Ellipsis of a constituent whose head has moved out of it (“headless ellipsis”) is possible in some cases but not in others. Headless ellipsis is licensed only if the stranded head has not crossed a Spell-Out domain. The reason is that the silencing instruction responsible for ellipsis must be PF-visible on the head of the elided constituent, and PF-visibility is cut off at Spell-Out domain boundaries. A parallel effect is observed with remnants of head movement that are frozen for movement (“headless movement”). The two effects can possibly be united if ellipsis and copy deletion recruit the same silencing instruction at PF, hosted on the head of the deleted constituent. A third, mirror-image effect is observed with reprise fragments, which must be visibly headed. This time head movement removes the PF instruction that spares these fragments from ellipsis. Overall, these phenomena establish the significance of headedness for the syntax-PF interface.

Landau, Idan. 2020. “A Scope Argument Against T-to-C Movement in Sluicing”. Syntax 23 (4): 375-93. https://doi.org/https://doi.org/10.1111/synt.12204.

Most accounts of sluicing assume it is derived by TP deletion at PF; however, C′ deletion is a viable option, which is even better equipped to explain the Sluicing–Comp Generalization. Nonetheless, this article shows that C′ deletion must be rejected, because it predicts scope enhancement for modals that raise to C in sluicing when in fact they take scope in T or below it. An implication is that some independent principle must block T-to-C movement under sluicing. The results further confirm that head movement must be a syntactic operation insofar as it affects semantic interpretation.

2018

Landau, Idan. 2018. “Direct Variable Binding and Agreement in Obligatory Control”. In "Pronouns in Embedded Contexts at the Syntax-Semantics Interface", edited by Pritty Pattel-Grosz, Patrick Georg Grosz, and Sarah Zobel, 1-41. Dordrecht: Springer International Publishing. https://doi.org/"10.1007/978-3-319-56706-8_1".

Standard semantic theories of Obligatory Control (OC) capture the obligatory de se reading of PRO but fail to explain why it agrees with the controller. Standard syntactic theories of OC explain the agreement but not the obligatory de se reading. A new synthesis is developed to solve this fundamental problem, in which the controller directly binds a variable in the edge of the complement. The associated semantics utilizes the idea that de se attitudes can be modelled as a special case of de re attitudes. The specific interaction of feature transmission and phase-based locality derives a striking universal asymmetry: Inflection on the embedded verb blocks OC in attitude complements but not in nonattitude complements. A semantic benefit is a straightforward account for unexpected binding between PRO and de re reflexives/pronouns.

Landau, Idan. 2018. “Missing Objects in Hebrew: Argument Ellipsis, Not VP Ellipsis”. Glossa 3 (1, 76.).

Hebrew is standardly cited as a language exhibiting Verb-stranding VP-ellipsis (VSVPE). Systematic reassessment of the data demonstrates that all the alleged evidence for VSVPE is consistent with Argument Ellipsis (AE); furthermore, there are ample data that are only consistent with AE, and more revealingly, data that can only be explained if VSVPE is unavailable. Finally, the verb preceding the missing object need not match the antecedent verb, falsifying the “Verb Identity Requirement”. The conclusion that Hebrew employs AE (similarly to East Asian languages) but not VSVPE focuses attention both on the typology of AE and on the so-far hidden constraints against VSVPE derivations.

2017

Landau, Idan. 2017. “Adjunct Control Depends on Voice”. In A Pesky Set: Papers for David Pesetsky, edited by Claire Halpert, Hadas Kotek, and Coppe van Urk, 93-102. MITWPL.

Nonfinite adjuncts present a puzzle in that they seem to allow both Obligatory Control (OC) and Non-Obligatory control (NOC) readings, which are normally in complementary distribution. Extending the analysis of complement control, I propose that adjuncts can either project as predicative clauses, or one layer further, as logophoric clauses; each projection is uniquely paired with its own type of control. This picture allows us to state in compact terms, though not to resolve, another puzzle that was noted in the 1980s: Rationale clauses resist implicit agent control when passivized. I show that the effect is systematic and extends to other environments (copular main clauses and temporal adjuncts). The emerging generalization is that passive adjuncts resist NOC.

2016

Landau, Idan. 2016. “Agreement at PF: An Argument from Partial Control”. Syntax 19 (1): 79-109.

Controlled null subjects (PRO) are semantically bound variables that bear morphological features. In certain environments of partial control, the morphological ϕ‐features (specifically, [person]) and the semantic value of PRO diverge. A natural explanation of the fact that the [person] feature of PRO is uninterpreted is that it is assigned at Phonological Form (PF). Given that this feature participates in agreement relations, we conclude that agreement must be (optionally or exclusively) a PF phenomenon.

Landau, Idan. 2016. “DP-Internal Semantic Agreement: A Configurational Analysis”. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 34: 975-1020.

“Hybrid” nouns are known for being able to trigger either syntactic or semantic agreement, the latter typically occurring outside the noun’s projection. We document and discuss a rare example of a Hebrew noun that triggers either syntactic or semantic agreement within the DP. To explain this and other unusual patterns of nominal agreement, we propose a configurational adaptation of the CONCORD-INDEX distinction, originated in Wechsler and Zlatić (2003). Morphologically-rooted (=CONCORD) features are hosted on the noun stem while semantically-rooted (=INDEX) features are hosted on Num, a higher functional head. Depending on where attributive adjectives attach, they may display either type of agreement. The observed and unobserved patterns of agreement follow from general principles of selection and syntactic locality.

Landau, Idan. 2016. “Against The Null Comitative Analysis of Partial Control”. Linguistic Inquiry 47 (3): 572–580.

A growingly popular analysis holds that the plural interpretation of PRO in partial control arises from associating a singular PRO with a null comitative phrase. Three novel arguments are presented to demonstrate the inadequacy of this analysis.